For an Answer Home | Studies Index | Bibliography | Glossary |
The Bible Gateway | The Blue Letter Bible | The Greek New Testament | Greek & Hebrew Lexicons |
Topical Studies
Smart's Rule: A Critique Robert M. Bowman, Jr.
|
Since 2000, a particular claim concerning biblical Greek grammar known as �Smart�s rule� has been circulating on the Web. This rule is thought by its advocates to prove that in John 20:28 Thomas must have been speaking of two persons and not one when he said �My Lord and my God!� That is, the rule supposedly proves that Thomas was speaking of Jesus as his Lord but of the Father as his God. Oddly enough, I cannot find any exposition of the rule from Smart himself. Mr. Smart appears to be Martin Smart, who was and, I presume, still is a Jehovah�s Witness. Beyond that I have no information about Mr. Smart and have not seen anything in writing from him presenting or defending his own rule. Most of the references to Smart�s rule on the Web appear on a listserv known as B-Greek, in its archived discussions from late 2000 and early 2001 (http://www.ibiblio.org/bgreek/). Recently, on a listserv that I moderate (http://groups.yahoo.com/group/evangelicals_and_jws/), one of the list members touted Smart�s rule as superior to Sharp�s rule, which is a well-known and much-discussed rule of Greek grammar. Let us, then, take a look at Smart�s rule and see if there is anything to it. Defining
Smart�s Rule The writer who actually presented and defended Smart�s rule on B-Greek was a Jehovah�s Witness named Dan Parker. Here is how he defined the rule: �In native [not translation] KOINE Greek when the
copulative KAI connects two substantives of personal description in
regimen [i.e. both or neither have articles] and the first substantive
alone is modified by the personal pronoun in the genitive or the
personal pronoun is repeated for perspicuity [Winer 147-148;155] two
persons or groups of persons are in view.� Dan Parker, �Re:
John 20:28 and Smart�s rule. Correction,� B-Greek listserv, http://www.ibiblio.org/bgreek/test-archives/html4/2001-02/4231.html (bracketed material in original). Note that Smart�s rule as given by Parker actually covers four types of constructions: Article + Substantive + Pronoun + kai + Article + Substantive + Pronoun Substantive + Pronoun + kai + Article + Substantive + Pronoun Article + Substantive + Pronoun + kai + Article + Substantive Substantive + Pronoun + kai + Article + Substantive It does not matter whether the pronoun precedes or follows the substantive. The way that Smart�s rule is worded, it may seem to be qualified in such a way that it need not apply to all texts using the third and fourth constructions (i.e., those that do not repeat the pronoun �for perspicuity�). However, from Parker�s contention that the rule proves that John 20:28 is speaking of two persons, I infer that what he (and presumably Smart) mean is that whenever the pronoun is repeated with the second substantive the repetition is for the sake of perspicuity and that in all such cases the second noun still refers to someone different than the first substantive. According to Parker, then, the rule has no exceptions in biblical Greek when the following conditions are met:
The
Repetition of the Pronoun As already noted, in constructions thought to be governed by Smart�s rule a pronoun in the genitive case must be attached to the first substantive and may be attached to the second substantive �for perspicuity.� I am not sure why this qualification is attached since Parker and others who endorse the rule seem to think that it applies to any text in which the pronoun is repeated with the second substantive. As stated, the rule refers to a few pages in Winer to document this idea of the repetition of the pronoun for perspicuity. The fact is that Winer was not referring to a doubling of the same pronoun or even necessarily the use of two pronouns. Rather, he was speaking of the use of a pronoun that in some sense is redundant but is used because the antecedent is already several words or more distant:
The NT texts that Winer cites as examples of his point often do not even use two pronouns. Instead, they use a pronoun to refer back to an antecedent substantive that is far enough back in a somewhat complex sentence structure, so that the pronoun helps to make the antecedent clearer: �The people who sat in darkness have seen a great light, and to those who were sitting in the land and shadow of death, a light has dawned to them [autois]� (Matt. 4:16). �Now when he had gone out to the entrance, another woman saw him [auton]�� (Matt. 26:71). �Therefore, the one who knows the good
thing to do and does not do [it], to
him [aut�] it is sin�
(James In Winer�s other examples, sometimes two pronouns
are used and they are the same (Acts As best I can tell, then, Winer�s treatment of the pronoun used for perspicuity has no bearing or relevance to Smart�s rule. Alleged
Examples of Smart�s Rule In one of his posts to B-Greek, Dan Parker offered the following lists of examples of texts fitting Smart�s rule. This same list has appeared verbatim elsewhere, notably on a web site defending Jehovah�s Witness doctrine (�An Online Response to a Kevin Quick Defender." The website where this article originally appeared has been taken down. As of Aug. 2005, it is available for purchase at the following site: http://www.geocities.com/yhwhbible/main.htm) Possessive pronoun repeated for perspicuity (21) - (Mt 12:47,49; Mk 3:31 ,32 ,33 ,34 ; 6:4 7:10 ; 8:20, 21 Lu 8:21; Jn 2:12; 4:12; Ac 2:17; Ro 16:21 ; 1Th 3:11 ; 2Th 2:16 ; 1Ti 1:1; 2Ti 1:5; Heb 8:11; Re 6:11) [Heb 1:7 is a LXX quote and is therefore translation Greek.] Single possessive - both substantives anarthrous (10) - (Mk 3:35; Ro 1:7; 1Co 1:3; 2Co 1:2; Ga 1:3; Ep 1:2; Php 1:2; 2Th 1:1,2; Phil 1:3) Single possessive pronoun - both substantives arthrous (12) - (Mk 6:21; 10:7,19; 16:7; Lk 2:23; 14:26; 18:20; Jn 11:5; Eph 6:2; Ac 7:14; 10:24; Re 11:18) This is the only list I have been able to find of alleged examples. Before going any further, some corrections to the
list of verse references are needed. The first paragraph appears to cite
Mark 8:20, 21, followed by Luke 8:21, but in fact the first two
references should be to Luke 8:20, 21 (so that the next one is actually
a repeat). There are thus only 20 verses listed in the first paragraph.
In the second paragraph, �Phil 1:3� is a reference to Philemon 3. In
the third paragraph, the first reference in Luke should be to Luke 2:33,
not Next, in the interest of giving Smart�s rule
every chance, we should take note of other texts that appear to fit its
parameters successfully. I have found a few other such references:
Matthew 12:50; We have, then, 42 references listed by Dan Parker
(not 43, since he accidentally counted Luke The
Semantics of Conjoined Substantives The first question that needs to be asked about these example texts is whether there would be any possibility of the substantives being understood as referring to a single referent regardless of the articles or pronouns attached to them. The answer in most of these texts is an unequivocal no. The semantic relation between the substantives alone is enough to make their different referents unambiguous. In 26 of our 45 examples, the substantives include terms designating family relationships that must be held by different individuals. These include: �
6 texts that speak of a person�s father and mother (Mark
�
12 texts that speak of a person�s mother, brothers, and
sisters (Matt. In addition, the texts include references to the following: �
sons and daughters (Acts � Timothy�s grandmother and mother (2 Tim. 1:5) �
one�s father, mother, wife, children, brothers, and
sisters (Luke �
Jesus (referred to as �he�) and his mother, brothers,
and disciples (John � Jacob (�himself�), his sons, and his cattle (!) (John 4:12) � Martha, her sister, and Lazarus (John 11:5) �
Jacob his (Joseph�s) father and all his relatives (Acts �
Cornelius�s relatives and friends (Acts Since it is impossible for any of these texts to be referring to a single individual, or even to be using the conjoined plural nouns to refer to the same group (since one�s sons cannot also be one�s daughters or one�s cattle, for example!), these texts cannot tell us anything as to the possible semantic significance of the placement of the possessive pronouns with regard to the nouns not having the same referent. Twelve of the remaining examples refer to God the
Father and to Jesus Christ (Rom. 1:7; 1 Cor. 1:3; 2 Cor. 1:2; Gal. 1:3;
Eph. 1:2; Phil. 1:2; 1 Thess. 3:11; 2 Thess. 1:1, 2; 2:16; 1 Tim. 1:1;
Phm. 3). All but two of these (1 Thess. This leaves only seven examples of constructions supposedly governed by Smart�s rule. That isn�t much on which to base a rule of grammar. But let�s look at these remaining texts to see what evidence they might yield in support of Smart�s rule. Weak
Support for the Rule In Mark 6:4, Jesus says, �A prophet is not without honor except in his hometown and among his relatives and in his household.� There are two reasons for questioning whether this text fits the parameters of Smart�s rule at all. First, the terms �hometown� (patris) and �household� (oikia) do not describe persons in the way that �relative� (sungen�s) does. Rather, they refer to entities composed of persons. I am unsure whether Smart�s rule could be extended to include such substantives, assuming the rule were valid. Second and more telling, the three nouns are not simply connected by kai, as Smart�s rule assumes, but are parts of three prepositional phrases using en (�in,� �among�) connected by kai. That having been said, in this instance we do not have terms referring to separate referents. Jesus� statement proceeds from the largest unit (his hometown) to a subset of that unit (his relatives) to a subset of that unit (his own family or household). Mark In Mark 16:7, the angel at the tomb tells the women to tell �his disciples and Peter.� Of course, Peter was one of Jesus� disciples, so here again, as in Mark 6:4, the second term is a subset of the first. In Romans 16:21, Paul writes, �Timothy my fellow worker greets you, and also Lucius and Jason and Sosipater, my kinsmen.� Grammatically, Paul connects the four proper names together with kai; the expression �my fellow worker� is in apposition to �Timothy� and the expression �my kinsmen� is in apposition to the other three names. This text, then, is a dubious example of Smart�s rule. Hebrews Revelation Finally, Revelation Of these seven texts, only one clearly fits what
Smart�s rule claims (that the two substantives have different
referents), namely, Mark More
Counterexamples to Smart�s Rule So far I have found two more clear counterexamples to Smart�s rule. 2
Corinthians 8:23. �As for Titus, he is my
partner and fellow worker among you [koin�nos
emos kai eis humas sunergos]�.�
Note that the nouns �partner� (koin�nos)
and �fellow worker� (sunergos)
both explicitly describe the same person, namely, Titus. This text,
then, is a clear counterexample to Smart�s rule. Philippians 2:25. �But I thought it necessary to send to you Epaphroditus, my brother and fellow worker and fellow soldier (ton adelphon kai sunergon kai sustrati�t�n mou), who is also your messenger and minister to my need (hum�n de apostolon kai leitourgon t�s xreias mou).� Remarkably, in this one verse we have an illustration of Sharp�s rule in the first half of the verse and a clear counterexample of Smart�s rule in the second half of the verse. The noun string ton adelphon kai sunergon kai sustrati�t�n perfectly fits Sharp�s rule. The second noun string describing Epaphroditus, hum�n de apostolon kai leitourgon t�s xreias mou, fits the syntax structure of Smart�s rule (possessive pronoun�noun�kai�noun, with the two anarthrous nouns in regimen), yet the nouns both have the same referent. Therefore, this text also is a clear counterexample to Smart�s rule. Conclusion Smart�s rule finds all of its support in texts where the two or three nouns in regimen must have different referents because of the semantics of the nouns in question (e.g., father and mother, or mother and sons). In texts where this is not the case, more often than not the nouns do not have separate referents. Sometimes the referents are overlapping, or one refers to a subset of the other noun; and sometimes the referent is identical. The bottom line is that the presence or absence of
a possessive pronoun has no bearing on the exegesis of phrases in which
two or more substantives are connected by kai.
Where the substantives are in regimen (all having the article or all
lacking the article), the meaning of the terms in context is the only
real consideration in determining whether the substantives have one or
more referent. In texts where the substantives used are generally
synonyms, as in John |